Decolonizing Philosophy without Further Delay: Acorn Editors Respond to the Oxford Student Collective

Anthony Neal, Greg Moses, and Gail Presbey

 

Philosophy as a Way of Black Life

Anthony Sean Neal

Mississippi State University


I am a free being of consciousness, but by vocation, I am a missionary of sorts, to language, history, and phenomena... attempting to convert them to the truth!

What is philosophy about for me? → the nature of perceptual frameworks and philosophical experiences

My interest in philosophy at the moment is strictly humanist. I would probably characterize my thoughts as existential humanist to be more precise. As Alfred North Whitehead once wrote, “I want to live, to live well, and to live better.” This comes with the requirement that I focus time wrestling with the Augustinian queries: Who am I? and What do I want? I also take up the query put forward by Howard Thurman, “What will I do (to get what I want)?” However, my quest is not solipsistic in nature. I must also make an attempt to wrestle with the time and space of my existence. My first attempt to make such a philosophical assessment of the world along with a similar proclamation came when I was just nine years old. “Mommy, why do white people hate Black people?” She responded by saying, “that’s just the way the world is.” So then I retorted, “Well then, I am mad at the world!” This statement was made after taking a general assessment of my fourth grade class, of which I was the only Black male. Obviously, this statement is not in the format of any of the philosophy we are generally taught in a philosophy department but it cuts to the core of what I consider to be an important function for philosophy. Philosophy in some way should provide humans with the means to have a philosophical experience, that is to say an experience of being able to make sense out of our immediate and even distant space and time. In this sense, philosophy, particularly as metaphysics, is the knowledge required to live and thrive. While I agree with Rorty, that philosophy is not the only discipline able to perform this function, I do believe when done well, it is among the most complete and best at doing so.   

It is not necessarily true to say that it is natural for humans to philosophize well, but all humans seem to have the capacity to philosophize and most do from time to time. All humans have experiential moments of which we must use reason to define. The significance of analyzing the experience of the moment, or the experiential moment, has much to do with the emphasis that I wish to place on the development of humans, generally speaking, and the development of particular persons or cultures.

First, how does the experiential moment happen? Next, when does the experiential moment take place? And finally, what evidence exists to suggest that the scheme being depicted -- that there exists the ability to analyze and assess the experiential moment -- is a likely scenario?

In order to demonstrate a resistant attitude towards my own presuppositions, these questions require an attempt to understand not only what precisely is being asked, but also what kinds of questions are being asked. This will help to determine what kind of answer(s) might be best fitted for such a question. It is imperative to acknowledge at the onset that the description of the experiential moment is not an exact science and that the concern here is with the ability to bring precision to the description of the experiential moment and therefore to show with the greatest probability, the actuality of its existence. An approximation of the actual experiential moment is an acceptable end. The realization that all moments are undeniably bound to other moments is not being disputed. However, the ability to use abstraction as a tool of human reason for the purpose of analysis does provide an opportunity to form an approximated description. The development into particular persons or cultures is also largely linked to an awareness of the self as an individual, and is based on perception, or knowledge of experience. Therefore, the answers to the previous questions of how, when, and what, are tied to, or are reliant upon knowledge in a very foundational manner.   

Now it is necessary to respond to the previous first question, put forward here secondly, which was how does the experiential moment happen? In answering this question, I will explain experiential moments as they pertain to blackness. This will demonstrate the importance of the possibility for a singular experiential event or set of multiple experiential events being relevant and meaningfully responsible for the shaping of a unique people or culture. A variety of considerations must immediately come to the fore, in order that the active process of this moment can be clearly understood. These range from the temporal-spatial positioning, socio-political conditions, existential concerns, to the perceptual frameworks learned and used as tools of interpretation. Initially the definition of experiential moment will be exposed, beginning with simple terms, and then expand, such that the definitional clarity gained will create enough space for this conceptual notion to add the greatest amount of force to the ancillary ideas being associated.

The experiential moment is the moment when we become simultaneously aware of an intelligible object through our senses and intellectually aware of that same object. The things that are not sensed in this manner are non-sensed objects to the human and are not experienced. The things that are not sensed in this manner are non-sensed objects to the human. The possibility of the things which can be experienced through our senses and our rational faculties include persisting ideas, objects, and qualities which objects possess. When objects are sensed in this manner, the function of reason or the intellect is to raise the sensory awareness of an object, or that which is intelligible, to the point of knowledge. This is an immediate event in that the object which is knowable is known the moment it is perceived. Of course, there is always room for the improvement or clarity of knowledge, but the fact remains that the object is known the moment it moves from possibility of knowledge to actual knowledge, which also speaks to the status of the knower as a knower of something.  As it pertains to being Black, particularly in its connection to the modern era, the significance of the experiential moment is found in how this process unfolds. Being Black is a shifting set of cultural performances produced by the experience of being Black at a particular moment in time. It is very much a product of the lived experience. There is not now nor has there ever been an essence attached to what it means to be Black that is formed exterior to the lived experience of blackness. Because there is no essence in having skin of a darker hue, the individual has to come to the knowledge of blackness on their own. The other factors mentioned above (temporal-spatial positioning, socio-political conditions, existential concerns, the perceptual frameworks learned and used as tools of interpretation) become determinate factors in what a knower knows when they come to possess the knowledge of blackness.

The experiential moment of blackness is also what gave energy to the claim in my first book, Common Ground (Africa World Press 2015), that community development and social transformation might be possible grounded in the consciousness derived from the shared experience of the phenomenon which was being blacked by law and oppressed because of the color of one’s skin or the color of one’s ancestor’s skin.  In that work, the argument used did not clearly bring to the fore the sense in which I was developing the notion of blackness as resulting from an existential moment of experience. This created the problem of portraying blackness as an inner essence, as opposed to coming about in the physical world under certain temporal-spatial conditions. These temporal-spatial conditions give way to the experience of being bound by the social constriction (I prefer constriction to construction) which is blackness. It is the social constriction which forces one into a community, whether physically or ideological. The community is based upon the perceptual frameworks that develop within and without those who are blacked by law and custom, such that a sense of who Black people are is held by Black people and others. This shared sense of what it means to be Black or white for that matter, which is only an approximation, is what was meant by the idea of a shared consciousness in Common Ground.

When I consider those who do African American Philosophy, I approach my reflections from the understanding that everyone will not arrive at the same conclusions based upon the methods used to frame questions and also the subject matter considered to be important. Some focus on the legitimacy of the philosophical subject (African American Philosophy) and its continued existence and others focus even on the subject philosophizing (the individual philosopher) with a desire and aim towards creating a space in which to continue philosophizing comfortably by arguing for inclusiveness. I think this is a noble aim, one that can give great rewards to the particular philosopher. However, I feel this aim is problematic because so limited in effect: the individual philosopher has a difficult time explaining the worth of such philosophy to more than a few philosophers.  But this could be just my issue. I typically lean towards the communal and not the individual when thinking of benefit.

Still others, who do African American Philosophy, can be consumed with correcting or showing proficiency with the western canon. I don't fault anyone for this because I expect people to be products of their education, but not forever. So what then...what is an alternative? It is my understanding that without the existence of the black body in the American space there would be no need for African American Philosophy and to that point, I don't think it can be good to divorce African American Philosophy from the black body or the experiences of black bodies as detailed in written works, through orality, through observation, or through one's own lived experience.

Early philosophers never really divorced their philosophy from their experience. Their experience was always their launching pad for thought. Of course, not all who do African American Philosophy must be black and I don't think all African Americans philosophers should do African American Philosophy, but if African American Philosophy is done, I feel it is a mistake to divorce it from the experience of being black and the black body. Howard Thurman speaks of the sense of fragmentation fueled by such a divorce: , “How can I believe life has meaning if I don’t believe my own life has meaning?” This statement is reminiscent of the concept that DuBois put forth in The Souls of Black Folk,

It is a peculiar sensation, this double-consciousness, this sense of always looking at one’s self through the eyes of others, of measuring one’s soul by the tape of a world that looks on in amused contempt and pity. One ever feels his two-ness, an American, a Negro; two souls, two thoughts, two unreconciled strivings; two warring ideals in one dark body, whose dogged strength alone keeps it from being torn asunder. The history of the American Negro is the history of this strife- this longing to attain self-conscious manhood, to merge his double self into a better and truer self. In this merging he wishes neither of the older selves to be lost. He does not wish to Africanize America, for America has too much to teach the world and Africa. He wouldn’t bleach his Negro blood in a flood of white Americanism, for he knows that Negro blood has a message for the world. He simply wishes to make it possible for a man to be both a Negro and an American without being cursed and spit upon by his fellows, without having the doors of opportunity closed roughly in his face. (p. 2-3).

My Philosophical House (of Ideas)

The thing that plagues me most, in terms of philosophical thought, is how I can develop a reasonable notion of freedom in light of existence? What has Blackness done to me? How does a proximal relationship to oppression disrupt moral decision making ability and my ? I also find it necessary to state that I am against oppression and for life.

For me, as a humanistically focused (which pertains to my subject matter) (h)umanist philosopher (which pertains to my method of interrogating the problem), this problem begins as a problem of interpretation, one to be solved through a dialectical method of interrogating the past through a method of processual hermeneutic phenomenology.

African American philosophy or philosophy of the black experience seeks to discover definitions, categories, and the existential conditions of blackness, but also to provide a rigorous and robust treatment of the same, where none exists. The intent in doing so is not only one of discovery, but also to put forth empirical as well normative claims useful in addressing hindrances to whatever qualifies as a flourishing life. Existentially, the fundamental problem of any humanistically focused philosophy has to be human survival and flourishing. If this is true then the fundamental problem of blackness is survival as an object of oppression in an oppressive society. Examples questions the Philosophy of the Black Experience brings to the fore:

1.   What role does oppression perform in the formation of a culture?

2.   What are the necessary or sufficient tools for mitigating an oppressed reality?

The Philosophy of the Black Experience roots the study of black as a type, and not as a the color of skin…

Although the topic is often neglected as framed by the parameters as stated in the example questions above Philosophy of the Black Experience, neglect is not the same as irrelevance in this matter. In fact, the opposite claim moves more in the direction of truth, particularly when it is considered that within definitive claims of just what does philosophy do, or to what problems does philosophy attend, one salient response is to focus upon the problem(s) of human existence. To this end, Leonard Harris’s Philosophy Born of Struggle’s demonstrates how identifying categories can assist in making the subject and subject matter better known’ Stephen Ferguson’s Philosophy of African American Studies brings attention to the neglect of this subject as a direct result of institutional structures that inhibit work which suffers from the realization of legitimacy and justification by college and university administrators. Also, the book by Ferguson along with McClendon demonstrates how this work has historically progressed in spite of the lack of resources and recognition as relevant from the same administrators. George Yancy provides a similar scope, albeit abbreviated, focusing on contemporary African American Philosophers in African-American Philosophers: 17 Conversations.

References below.

 

 

Resisting the Death of Language

Greg Moses

Texas State University

My work today concerns the liberation of language. We begin at the portal of death: at the moment where language of the living calls out to those who cannot answer. In this moment language is abolished in the vacuum of someone’s final inability to cry out. Therefore, we speak of social death. When language is alive, there is a talk-back, a dialectic, and moments-to-come. In the social death of language, living authority speaks down, sentencing other voices to unheard death.

In the social vortex that howled around the murder of George Floyd, Jr., language was strangled first. Victim and witnesses spoke up and out, but they were not authorized to communicate anything of consequence. Centurions of social death guarded the corridor to death itself. Then Darnella Frazier, using the speed-of-light language of smart phone video and Facebook, spoke to the world. Between May 26, the day after Floyd’s murder, and August 22, as that summer drew to a close, the Armed Conflict Location & Event Data Project (ACLED) recorded over 11,000 demonstrations linked to the Black Lives Matter (BLM) movement at more than 3,000 locations in all 50 states and Washington, DC (ACLED 2021). Creosote Mapper located 4,446 cities or towns worldwide that expressed protest, with heavy coverage in Europe (“Black Lives” 2020). In response to the strangulation of language and life on May 25 came an outcry.

As the global speak-out rolled across the planet, a collective of students at Oxford University on June 30, 2020, issued an open letter on “diversifying the philosophy faculty and curriculum at oxford.” With explicit appeal to the voices of BLM protest, the students pushed “for swift and systemic representational and curriculum change within the philosophy faculty.” And they shared their homework. The letter from the Diversifying Philosophy Student Collective, signed by more than 250 students, appended a document with suggested readings, topics, and methodologies for “swift and systemic” change (OxfordPublicPhilosophy.com). They argued in part:

“We understand that the path to change is complex; but we think the urgency of change supersedes the difficulties: we must do all we can to learn about currently under-discussed topics and to support minority academics, in structures whose curricula can either perpetuate systemic oppression and silencing or strive to envision a just future.”

“We must begin to take steps to remedy the effects of systemic racism, sexism, and much more that pervade our discipline. This might involve a learning curve. We understand student demand is also a deciding factor towards making changes. We want you to know this demand exists, and we want to help build active feedback and communication systems to promote faculty-student interaction in combating structural injustices.”

The student letter appealed to a liberation of language. Vivacious language, crying up from the streets, aroused students to a recognition that they could no longer not talk about key topics that had been languishing “under-discussed.” Structures of instruction perpetuated wary “silencing.” Students offered themselves up as peacemakers and healers; they presented themselves as interlocutors who could nurture language practices to life through “active feedback and communication systems” that would “promote faculty-student interaction in combating structural injustices.”

To assess the effect of the letter, students have brought a looking glass—the concept of structural injustice. With precise insight into structural injustice, any unflinching witness can gaze deeply into isomorphic connections that collaborate with the power of indifference and the death of language as was intersected in Minneapolis on the last Monday of May, 2020, near the curbside of E. 38th St. at Chicago Ave., on or about 8:20 PM GMT -5.

When and Where to Get Started

As for myself, when the student letter hit the term “learning curve,” I was transported to another city street just outside the gates of a university in Atlanta, Georgia. As a graduate student there, I stepped from that curb onto a city bus during one afternoon’s rush hour. With a head full of philosophy seminars gyrating my thoughts, I bounded up the stairs of that bus and turned to face two packed columns of seats filled with the tired eyes of Black workers going home. In less than an instant, a hard question was conveyed to my body entire. I could feel the structural force of an impact. An oracle paraphrased the great Socratic challenge: Who do you think you are? Soon after that turning point, I began to shift my philosophic center from Deweyan pragmatism to Kingian nonviolence. And part of this shift involved an intensive self-study in Africana philosophy. Thirty-five years later, I am still walking up that learning curve.

Since my early days as a novice college teacher in the late 1980s, I have used my syllabus, not only as a place for texts that were well taught to me, but as a place to explore other voices. Over the years, these other voices have included works by and words attributed to non-Europeans such as Cheikh Anta Diop, Ptah-hotep, The Eloquent Peasant, Vyasa, Gandhi, Laozi, Kongzi, Mengzi, Imam Ali, Al-Kindi, The Brethern of Purity, Buddha Shakyamuni, Angela Davis, George Jackson, Howard Thurman, Martin Luther King, Jr., Black Elk, Dekanawida, Gloria Anzaldua, or the Mayan authors of the Popol Vuh. But the learning curve also includes other voices within the European sphere, such as Hovamol, The Schleithiem Confession, Spinoza, or Marx.

As students have affirmed in their open letter, when you are on a learning curve you make mistakes. Re-education is complex and there are difficulties, but as the students go on to argue, “the urgency of change supercedes the difficulties.” With understated insight, the open letter observes that “it would be almost inconsistent reasoning to debar work in these philosophies by such a premise as not being adequately acquainted with their cultural milieu” (“open letter”).

How can we say it is unwise to get started today because we failed to get started yesterday? In college, especially, we must ever begin to teach curricula that we have never been trained to teach. And this is what the students want to see teachers doing in a “swift and systemic” movement. This is not a very difficult thing to do for college teachers, who should be on some kind of learning curve at all times. Look for other voices. Bring them to class. As students have argued, first you diversify, then you catch up. You keep trying to keep up. We have come to a world historical moment when we might sing out that those not busy with other voices are busy killing language.

As I once argued to a college teacher who was fresh out of graduate school, but who had not been prepared to teach other voices:  “Yes, you will get some things wrong. But what is that wrong compared to the wrong of putting it off?” Oxford students argue that they can’t wait. And yet, students are met with voices who, without irony, in the third decade of the 21st century, argue that there should be no hurry. Ethnographers can explore the cultural milieu of whiteness and its sense of time. Meanwhile, the wrong thing to do is to put off curriculum transformation until next term. Teaching only the voices of the existing canon subtracts language and life from philosophy and philosophizing.

Racism, Marx, and the Social Turn

To students and allies who are very new to these curriculum battles, I offer three brief groundwork advisories: (1) public language on racism is arrayed against you, (2) don’t forget Marx (or Wilderson’s Afropessimist caution about humanism), and (3) demilitarize how we imagine revolution.

Public language on racism suffers a great deal from dictionaries that must reflect common usage. Since common usage is embedded within racist structures of injustice, the dictionary is more likely to support confusion than dispel it. This is one reason why discussions of anti-racism are especially suited to philosophical discourse, where terms may be locally defined aside from their dictionary denotations. The open letter uses the term “systemic racism,” which the OED defines in a helpful way. But the dictionary should warn us that the unmodified term “racism” very nearly contradicts the term modified by “systemic.” As tools of analysis, each term has quite different uses. And their lexical ordering is crucial. In order to avoid all kinds of silly detours, the unmodified term “racism” must be understood as conceptually derivative of its “systemic” partner. And this is why I like to remember one of my favorite British philosophers, Karl Marx, progenitor of systemic critique.

I like to remember that Marx spent more than half his life in London where he wrote Das Kapital largely on the basis of archival research at British libraries, walking streets that were illustrated in the glorious fictions of Charles Dickens. I ask the reader’s permission, as I often beg my students, to please allow me to speak of the philosopher who was buried at Highgate some three and a half decades before the Bolshevik Revolution. Let us take a moment to consider what communism meant to Marx before it meant many other things to the world after Lenin.

The young philosopher Marx defined our general terms of struggle when he wrote the ninth and tenth “Theses on Feuerbach.” In thesis nine, Marx discerned that even the materialists of his age were individualistic in their philosophy, conceiving of society as nothing but the sum of its individual members. Then, in thesis ten, Marx indicated a need to conceptualize “social humanity” (marxists.org). Today when we criticize the logic of neoliberalism, we reaffirm Marx’s insight. Or when we point out the contrary definitions of “racism” and “systemic racism,” what are we doing but minding the gap between theses nine and ten, insisting upon that social turn, too.

Since we have introduced the term “humanity,” and since we are on a learning curve with other voices, we cannot allow the term to stand uncontested. Frank Wilderson states the objection succinctly in Afropessimism:

“If, as Afropessimism argues, Blacks are not Human subjects, but are instead structurally inert props, implements for the execution of White and non-Black fantasies and sadomasochistic pleasures, then this also means that, at a higher level of abstraction, the claims of universal humanity that the above theories all subscribe to are hobbled by a meta-aporia: a contradiction that manifests whenever one looks seriously at the structure of Black suffering in comparison to the presumed universal structure of all sentient beings.” (Wilderson 2020, 15)

The “social humanity” of the young Marx must be interrogated for its implicit participation in colonial whiteness. Who are the workers of the world? The language of critical dialectic thrives here.

Wilderson’s life is but one witnesses to a continuum of revolutionary activity, including the real-life power that comes from an ability to issue credible threats. So I will not today argue that revolution should be defined globally as nonviolent. However, I am arguing that there are quite a few local situations—some of them quite extensive in time and space—where resistance grows power by reversing cycles of violence. A new curriculum should not neglect to study the philosophy of revolution that demilitarizes the imagination. Authorities could include Dekanawida, Elizabeth Heyrick, Gandhi, Jane Addams, Bayard Rustin, MLK, Jr., Thich Nhat Hanh, Cesar Chavez, Johan Galtung, Gene Sharp, or Erica Chenoweth, to name a few (The Acorn, n.d.).

The Oxford student collective is well begun. You are cultivating a new philosophy via Zoom and YouTube. You are contributing to a revolution in the history of philosophy. We can see that mountain top. Your initiative is necessary and urgent. The timing of it does credit to the memory of George Floyd, Jr. and Black Lives Matter. We can’t wait (King [1963] 2010).

References below.

 

 Ethics from Multiple Sources

Gail Presbey

University of Detroit Mercy

Park, Peter K.J. 2013. Africa, Asia, and the History of Philosophy: Racism in the Formation of the Philosophical Canon, 1780–1830. SUNY Press.

I want to build on some of Greg Moses’ remarks, with some examples of how I have tried to present a more globally inclusive approach to Ethics. My interests in cross-cultural philosophy began early, first as an interest in world religions, backed up by a passion to travel the world. My father played a role in this. When I was 13 years old, he gave me a book called The Practical Cogitator. It was an anthology of writings by pragmatists and transcendentalist philosophers, for the most part. And as we know now, Ralph Waldo Emerson and Henry David Thoreau, among others, were very influenced by their study of what has widely been called by the Anglophone world ‘Eastern’ philosophy (Sherman).  Back when Emerson and Thoreau were studying (and earlier) philosophy survey books routinely began with ancient Egyptian, Jewish, Sanskrit and Chinese sources (Park, 2013, 69-77).

Struhl, Karsten J. 1975. Ethics in Perspective: A Reader. New York: Random House.

Presbey, Gail M., Karsten J. Struhl, Richard E. Olsen (Eds.). 1995 (First edition), 2000 (Second edition). The Philosophical Quest: A Cross-Cultural Reader. New York: McGraw-Hill publishers.

When I first began studying philosophy in the late 1900s, not as many philosophical survey books produced in the United States were interested in philosophical contributions from India, Africa, and Latin America, for example. Most such introductory books as well as graduate school syllabi routinely focused almost exclusively on white male European and Euro-American philosophers. However, there was one exception to this. Early on in my teaching career I found Karsten Struhl’s Ethics in Perspective. After teaching it a few years, I had a chance to meet the author/ editor of that helpful textbook. He and I, along with Richard Olsen (now deceased) came up with our own textbook, The Philosophical Quest: A Cross-Cultural Reader, back in 1995. Both of my co-editors were inspired by Buddhism, with Richard becoming a monk in a monastery in South Asia for several years. We wanted to juxtapose the various approaches and positions on the same topic next to each other, so that readers could decide which argument was most convincing to themselves – or at least to realize that much of what they might take for granted is not at all presumed in other philosophical traditions.

 

Our text back then also wanted to address the need for social change and the philosophical debates about the methods of change. Drawing on applied Buddhism, Sulak Sivaraksa argued that ignorance and craving were at the root of contemporary problems of consumerism, corruption and militarism, leading to injustice and impoverishment. Enrique Dussel argued that a liberation philosophy distinguishes the violence of the oppressed from that of the oppressors, while Gandhi and King argued for nonviolent means to reach nonviolent ends. Philosophy, we hoped, could help to shed light on the world’s problems as well as suggest ways forward.

Dussel, Enrique. 2013. Ethics of Liberation in the Age of Globalization and Exclusion. Edited by Alejandro A. Vallega. Translated by Nelson Maldonado-Torres, Eduardo Mendieta, Yolanda Angulo, Camilo Pérez Bustillo. Durham and London: Duke University Press.

[Thiruvalluvar], Tirukkural. 1982. English Translation and Commentary by G. U. Pope, W. H. Drew, John Lazarus and F. W. Ellis. First published by W.H. Allen, & Co, 1886, Reprinted by The South India Saiva Siddhantha Works Publishing Society, Tinnevelly, Madras, India , 1962, 1982. Accessed online through Project Madurai, https://www.projectmadurai.org/pm_etexts/pdf/pm0153.pdf

Anonymous, 1969. “Egyptian Didactic Tales” [including “A Dispute over Suicide” and “The Protests of the Eloquent Peasant”], translated by John A. Wilson, in Ancient Near Eastern Texts Relating to the Old Testament, Third Edition with Supplement, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 405-410.

What I want to share with you here are some of the texts I have used lately to present ethics to my students. Many of these texts I discovered since last publishing the reader mentioned above. Nowadays, I like to begin at the beginning of our current timeline, so I start with the introduction to Enrique Dussel’s large volume, Ethics of Liberation.  What moral theme can be found in the Egyptian Book of the Dead that is found centuries later in Old and New Testament writings? – the theme of justice. Dussel argues that rage about injustice and an insistence that injustice must be rectified (that is, a philosophy of liberation) can be found in the earliest ethical writings, whether we look at the Hammurabi Code or other ethical codes from the ancient world. At the ‘beginning of the beginning’ the topic of justice was not marginalized in ethics. We can also find compassion at the heart of early ethics documents, such as the argument for vegetarianism in ancient Tamil Literature such as the Thirukkural written by Thiruvalluvar (whose statue is prominently displayed on the campus of the School of Oriental and African Studies in London).

Then I like to cover ancient Egypt. “The Dialogue between a Man and His Ba” (2200-2050 BCE) is an important text. The man, the main character of the story, is so disillusioned by the injustice he finds that he longs for the afterlife instead. The Ba counters, and reminds him of his duties to other humans in this world. A recent archeological find provides the missing text of this ancient story, explaining that the man was physically sick due to his concern for the extent of injustice he saw. How important to not turn a blind eye to the world’s injustice, such as the George Floyd killing, but to feel the pain, see the systemic extent of the problem, and commit oneself to work in this world to change the system?

 

Any [the Scribe], “The Instruction of Any,” in Daniel Bonevac (Ed.), Beyond the Western Tradition: Readings in Moral and Political Philosophy. Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Publishing Co.

James, David. 1995. “’The Instruction of Any’ and Moral Philosophy,” in Albert Mosley (Ed.), African Philosophy: Selected Readings. Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 147-155.

Maybee, Julie E. 1999. “’The Instruction of Any”: An Ancient Egyptian Philosophical Theory of Ethics,” African Philosophy, 12/2.

Another ancient Egyptian text is the “Instruction of Any” (1648–1550 BCE). One can see a portrait of the scribe, Any, and his family, on the walls of the British Museum in their Ancient Egypt collection. These two texts which include debates challenge some naysayers who think that ancient Egypt only has pronouncements that don’t count as ethics because not mentioned in an argument. The former text had a debate between the man and his Ba (a dramatization of the internal debate within an individual – not unlike Descartes’ Meditations by his stove?). Here in the latter, Any, the father, gets into a debate with his son, Khonshotep, about the nature of moral education. They disagree on the list of the most important virtues for a person to embody. In our own times, David James (1995) argues that Khonshotep gets the better of the argument, while Julie Maybee (1999) argues that Any’s position is preferable and close to the ethics of care currently advocated by some feminist ethicists.

 

Jeffers, Chike. 2013. “Embodying Justice in Ancient Egypt: The Tale of the Eloquent Peasant as a Classic of Political Philosophy,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 21/3.

Another great text is the Tale of the Eloquent Peasant (1985-1773 BCE). The peasant is so upset at the injustice he has just suffered, that he gives an eloquent description of the just society. Chike Jeffers explores the details of the story, noting how the peasant, a rural person without pretensions, challenges the idea of who is wise, and who is to be listened to, in the halls of governmental power. All three of these texts are much older than any of the ancient Greek texts often cited as the birthplace of philosophy. But, as my students can attest, the issues they raise are perennial and are still relevant and debated today. Indeed, the Eloquent Peasant experiences the hands of the law similarly to the manner contested by the Black Lives Matter movement in the U.S. today (not to mention sister movements in Brazil and other countries who also deal with racially motivated violence by the police).

Spelman, Elizabeth V. 1998. “Aristotle and the Politicization of the Soul,” in Sterba, James (Ed.). 1998. Social and Political Philosophy: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. Second edition. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 74-82.

Cole, Eve Browning. 2000. “Women, Slaves, and ‘Love of Toil’ in Aristotle’s Moral Philosophy,” in James Sterba, Ed., Ethics: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 78-88.

Van Norden, Bryan. 2017. Taking Back Philosophy: A Multicultural Manifesto. New York: Columbia U. Press.

Rosemont, Henry. 2015. Against Individualism: A Confucian Rethinking of the Foundations of Morality, Politics, Family, and Religion. New York: Lexington Books.

Speaking of virtues, of course we must cover Aristotle’s theory of the virtues. While we recognize his greatness, we don’t want to ignore the problematic aspects of his texts. Contemporary philosophers like Elizabeth Spelman (1998) and Eve Browning Cole (2000) take him to task for his sexism as well as his support for social conventions like slavery. For example, why did Aristotle argue that reason was inconstant in woman, therefore leading to her supposed need to submit to man’s authority – her father or husband? Why did he not see the self-serving nature of his arguments that decide that it is in the best interest of some persons to submit themselves to the rule of others, as in the case of “natural” slaves? Aristotle’s ethics and political philosophy present the same arguments used during colonization to justify the enslavement of Africans and Native Americans (Churchill).

Confucian philosophy of the virtues arises earlier than Aristotle’s and with robust arguments. As Bryan van Norden aptly explains in his recent book, Taking Back Philosophy, philosophy doesn’t have to be expressed in only argument form. Yet, there are nonetheless plenty of examples of arguments in ancient Chinese and Indian philosophy. Furthermore contemporary Confucianists like Henry Rosemont argue that Confucianism is a helpful antidote to our Western emphasis on the individual at detriment to the community – a theme important to consider as our COVID-19 pandemic continues due to not only individual assertion of rights to flout precautions such as masking and social distancing, but also the short-sightedness of leaders of rich nation-states  ignoring the problems of the pandemic spreading in other countries caused by rich nations’ vaccine hoarding.

 

Waithe, Mary Ellen and Vicki Lynne Harper. 1987. “Late Pythagoreans: Theano II and Perictione II,” in Mary Ellen Waithe (Ed.), A History of Women Philosophers, Volume 1, 600 BC – 500 AD, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 41-48.

De Pizan, Christine. 2000. “The Book of the City of Ladies,” in James Sterba, Ed., Ethics: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press.

Yacob, Zera. “The Treatise of Zera Yacob,” in Daniel Bonevac (Ed.), Beyond the Western Tradition: Readings in Moral and Political Philosophy. Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Publishing Co.

Galawdewos, 2015. The Life and Struggles of Mother Walatta Petros. Translated and edited by Wendy Laura Belcher and Michael Kleiner. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Farley, Margaret. 2008. Just Love: A Framework for Christian Sexual Ethics. Continuum.

In face of the difficulty of finding writings by women in the ancient world, I appreciate Waithe and Harper’s making available the correspondence of the late Pythagorean, Theano II (4th to 3rd century BCE). Her writings witness her perceptivity and wisdom regarding family relations across gender and class (see Waithe, 41-58). In turning to Augustine, Aquinas, and natural law theory, we note what they have said about women. As a result we ask: in what ways are women philosophical friends and helpers to men? Is their role merely to procreate while men philosophize? There are many excellent feminist critics of Aquinas. Christine de Pizan was one of the first critics, writing her Book of the City of Ladies (first published in 1405) to challenge church teachings on women (and directly challenging Augustine’s City of God). While the early Modern European men still saw no place for women in philosophy, Zera Yacob in Ethiopia was writing his treatise where he argued, among other topics, that marriage was a partnership of equals, and Mother Walatta Petros was debating with the Portuguese Jesuits and defending Ethiopian Orthodox Christian philosophies (Galawdewos; Adamson and Jeffers). More recently, Margaret Farley’s Just Love argues that the “procreative norm” in much of Christian (for example) understanding of sexual morality is no longer relevant or humane.

 

Kant, Immanuel. 1983. “An Answer to the Question, What is Enlightenment? (1784),” Perpetual Peace and other Essays. Indianapolis: Hackett, 41-48.

Eze, Emmanuel. 1997. “The Color of Reason: The Idea of 'Race' in Kant's Anthropology.” In Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze (ed.), The Postcolonial Philosophy Reader. Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 103-140.

McCarthy, Thomas. 2009. Race, Empire, and the Idea of Human Development (Cambridge University Press, 2009).

Mills, Charles. 2000. “Kant’s Racial Views and their Implications,” in James Sterba, Ed., Ethics: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000, 172-78.

Langton, Rae, 2000. “Maria von Herbert’s Challenge to Kant,” in James Sterba, Ed., Ethics: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 201-211.

Kleingeld, Pauline. 2007. “Kant’s Second Thoughts on Race,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 57/229 (October), 586-592.

Many Ethics classes cover the moral theories of Immanuel Kant and John Stuart Mill at length. But, are Eurocentric philosophers in denial about the extent that these two theorists, who are well known for championing universal values such as human rights, nevertheless upheld hierarchical ideas about which races could reach full human moral development? As many scholars have noted, Kant argued that Africans could only follow orders and could not achieve moral autonomy. While one might get the impression after reading Kant’s essay, “What is Enlightenment?” (1784/1983) that he intended to encourage every human individual to think for themselves, we find out in his anthropological writings that he thought Asians, Africans, and Native Americans could not do this as well as Europeans (Emmanel Eze, Thomas McCarthy, Charles Mills). In other writings (Langton), we also find out that Kant is skeptical that European women could achieve these goals of Enlightenment, leaving only European men like himself capable of achieving full human personhood. We should read and teach texts that help us to understand the nuance of philosophers’ thoughts and theories when covering these topics such as work by Pauline Kleingeld (2007) who argues that Kant changed his position on these issues near the end of his life, criticizing certain actions of colonizers.

 

Bogues, Anthony. 2005. “John Stuart Mill and 'The Negro Question': Race, Colonialism, and the Ladder of Civilization.” In Andrew Valls, Ed., Race and Racism in Modern Philosophy. Oxford University Press, 217-234.

Smits, Katherine. 2008. “John Stuart Mill on the Antipodes: Settler Violence against Indigenous Peoples and the Legitimacy of Colonial Rule,” Australian Journal of Politics and History: Volume 54, Number 1, 2008, pp. 1-15.

Since John Stuart Mill worked for the British East India Company,  it may be no surprise to find out that his moral philosophy could be used to justify European colonization. But scholars like Anthony Bogues have delved into the details of Mill’s ethical theory applied to the colonies, and the picture that emerges is not flattering. Despite Mill’s forming the “Jamaica Committee,” according to Bogues, there are contradictions between some of Mill’s general ethical statements and Mill’s stance on colonialism in Jamaica and elsewhere. Katherine Smits likewise finds Mill’s evaluation of colonial actions in Australia and New Zealand to be fraught with problems. While Mill held out hope for the British civilizing mission, believing that the British could rule others for the benefit of their subjects, he denied repeated proof that in practice imperial rule does not improve the lives of those who are racially subordinated. Aren’t these grave shortcomings of Mill’s perspective worthy of study, if only to ensure this same colonial mindset does not endure as today’s Superpowers continue to presume they can (if only indirectly) rule others for the benefit of those others, while denying their own motives of gain?

 

Goodall, Jane. 1994. “Helping Kin in Chimpanzees,” in Peter Singer (Ed.), Ethics (Oxford Readers), First Edition. Oxford University Press.

De Waal, Franz. “Chimpanzee Justice,” in Peter Singer (Ed.), Ethics (Oxford Readers), First Edition. Oxford University Press.

Not wanting to practice speciesism, I try to introduce students to the ideas that humans are not the only beings to whom we owe moral concern. Peter Singer is one of the few prominent philosophers to create ethics textbooks that include animals. Jane Goodall and Franz de Waal argue that primates and other animals practice moral decision making and experience many moral sentiments that we previously thought were unique to humans. I turn to Native American texts to find sources that suggest to humans that we should learn from animals, taking certain animals and their special traits as role models and exemplars for us humans.

 

Churchill, Ward. 2000. “Perversions of Justice: Native American Examination of the Doctrine of U.S. Rights to Occupancy in North America,” in James Sterba, Ed., Ethics: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 401-418.

McKenna, Erin and Scott Pratt. 2015. American Philosophy: From Wounded Knee to the Present. London: Bloomsbury.

To James Sterba’s credit, in his 1998 and 2000 textbooks, he included Ward Churchill’s searing critique of the way John Locke’s philosophy was used to disenfranchise Native American communities, taking their land, labor, and lives. Sterba realized that when discussing ethics it was necessary to include multiple perspectives. How could Euro-Americans think that they had the world’s greatest philosophers, while Euro-American societies engaged in genocide against Native Americans, and then refused to acknowledge this crime, or justified their actions including through philosophy? Why are the philosophy texts to a large extent silent on this issue? A good exception is Erin McKenna and Scott Pratt’s book, American Philosophy: From Wounded Knee to the Present. There, they give an important account of Native American philosophy as well as African American and Latinx philosophy.

 

The problems of sexism and racism, misogyny, slavery and colonialism are not just in the past. They still permeate our contemporary world. In a philosophy class on ethics, these topics must be discussed. What good is ethics in our world filled with injustice, if it does not directly confront this injustice? Application alone is not the problem – the theories, theory-development process, and theorists are too. The theorists who came up with their seemingly abstract and universal theories were engaged in popularizing and defending views that justified slavery, colonialism and women’s subordination. Nowadays the same ideas disguise themselves as meritocracy, responsible governance, or good business practices. When we read philosophical texts from multiple perspectives, we can uncover white supremacist arguments  and hone our understanding of them in a centuries-long context. We can also see alternative philosophical theories that we may find more insightful and more life-giving. We can decide to embrace a different philosophical conception of the world.

References below.


References

ACLED (The Armed Conflict Location & Event Data Project). 2021. A Year of Racial Justice Protests: Key Trends in Demonstrations Supporting the BLM Movement. May 2021. https://acleddata.com/acleddatanew/wp-content/uploads/2021/05/ACLED_Report_A-Year-of-Racial-Justice-Protests_May2021.pdf

The Acorn: Philosophical Studies in Pacifism and Nonviolence. n.d. Accessed November 1, 2021. https://acornjournal.net/

Adamson, Peter and Chike Jeffers. 2020. The History of Philosophy without Any Gaps: Podcasts, Africana Series. https://historyofphilosophy.net/series/africana-philosophy

Anonymous, 1969. “Egyptian Didactic Tales” [including “A Dispute over Suicide” and “The Protests of the Eloquent Peasant”], translated by John A. Wilson, in Ancient Near Eastern Texts Relating to the Old Testament, Third Edition with Supplement, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 405-410.

Any [the Scribe], “The Instruction of Any,” in Daniel Bonevac (Ed.), Beyond the Western Tradition: Readings in Moral and Political Philosophy. Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Publishing Co.

“Black Lives Matter Protests 2020.” 2020. Last updated November 18, 2020. https://www.creosotemaps.com/blm2020/index.html

Bogues, Anthony. 2005. “John Stuart Mill and 'The Negro Question': Race, Colonialism, and the Ladder of Civilization.” In Andrew Valls, Ed., Race and Racism in Modern Philosophy. Oxford University Press, 217-234.

Churchill, Ward. 2000. “Perversions of Justice: Native American Examination of the Doctrine of U.S. Rights to Occupancy in North America,” in James Sterba, Ed., Ethics: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 401-418.

Cole, Eve Browning. 2000. Eve Browning Cole, “Women, Slaves, and ‘Love of Toil’ in Aristotle’s Moral Philosophy,” in James Sterba, Ed., Ethics: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 78-88.

Curtis, Charles Pelham and Ferris Greenslet, 1945. The Practical Cogitator; Or, The Thinker's Anthology. Houghton Mifflin. 

De Pizan, Christine. 2000. “The Book of the City of Ladies,” in James Sterba, Ed., Ethics: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press.

De Waal, Franz. “Chimpanzee Justice,” in Peter Singer (Ed.), Ethics (Oxford Readers), First Edition. Oxford University Press.

Du Bois, W. E. B. 2020. The Souls of Black folk: Essays and Sketches.

Dussel, Enrique. 2013. Ethics of Liberation in the Age of Globalization and Exclusion. Edited by Alejandro A. Vallega. Translated by Nelson Maldonado-Torres, Eduardo Mendieta, Yolanda Angulo, Camilo Pérez Bustillo. Durham and London: Duke University Press.

Eze, Emmanuel. 1997. “The Color of Reason: The Idea of 'Race' in Kant's Anthropology.” In Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze (ed.), The Postcolonial Philosophy Reader. Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 103-140.

Farley, Margaret. 2008. Just Love: A Framework for Christian Sexual Ethics. Continuum.

Ferguson, Stephen C. 2016. Philosophy of African American Studies: Nothing Left of Blackness. Palgrave MacMillan.

Galawdewos, 2015. The Life and Struggles of Mother Walatta Petros. Translated and edited by Wendy Laura Belcher and Michael Kleiner. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Goodall, Jane. 1994. “Helping Kin in Chimpanzees,” in Peter Singer (Ed.), Ethics (Oxford Readers), First Edition. Oxford University Press.

Harris, Leonard. 2000. Philosophy born of struggle: anthology of Afro-American philosophy from 1917. Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt Pub. Co.

James, David. 1995. “’The Instruction of Any’ and Moral Philosophy,” in Albert Mosley (Ed.), African Philosophy:  Selected Readings. Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 147-155.

Jeffers, Chike. 2013. “Embodying Justice in Ancient Egypt: The Tale of the Eloquent Peasant as a Classic of Political Philosophy,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 21/3.

Kant, Immanuel. 1983. “An Answer to the Question, What is Enlightenment? (1784),” Perpetual Peace and other Essays. Indianapolis: Hackett, 41-48. 

King, Martin Luther, Jr. (1963) 2010. “Letter from Birminghan Jail.” In Why We Can’t Wait, 85-110. Boston: Beacon Press, 2010.

Kleingeld, Pauline. 2007. “Kant’s Second Thoughts on Race,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 57/229 (October), 586-592.

Langton, Rae, 2000. “Maria von Herbert’s Challenge to Kant,” in James Sterba, Ed., Ethics: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 201-211.

Maybee, Julie E. 1999. “’The Instruction of Any”: An Ancient Egyptian Philosophical Theory of Ethics,” African Philosophy, 12/2.

McCarthy, Thomas. 2009. Race, Empire, and the Idea of Human Development (Cambridge University Press, 2009).

McClendon, John H., and Stephen C. Ferguson. 2019. African American Philosophers and Philosophy: An Introduction to the History, Concepts, and Contemporary Issues.

McKenna, Erin and Scott Pratt. 2015. American Philosophy: From Wounded Knee to the Present. London: Bloomsbury.

Mills, Charles. 2000. “Kant’s Racial Views and their Implications,” in James Sterba, Ed., Ethics: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000, 172-78.

Neal, Anthony Sean. 2015. Common Ground: A Comparison of the Ideas of Consciousness in the Writings of Howard W. Thurman and Huey P. Newton.

Park, Peter K.J.  2013. Africa, Asia, and the History of Philosophy: Racism in the Formation of the Philosophical Canon, 1780–1830. SUNY Press.

Paul, Sherman, 1958. The Shores of America: Thoreau’s Inward Exploration. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

Presbey, Gail M., Karsten J. Struhl, Richard E. Olsen (Eds.). 1995 (First edition), 2000 (Second edition). The Philosophical Quest: A Cross-Cultural Reader. New York: McGraw-Hill publishers.

Rorty, Richard. 2018. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature.

Rosemont, Henry. 2015. Against Individualism:  A Confucian Rethinking of the Foundations of Morality, Politics, Family, and Religion. New York:  Lexington Books.

Smit, Catherine. 2008. “John Stuart Mill on the Antipodes: Settler Violence against Indigenous Peoples and the Legitimacy of Colonial Rule,” Australian Journal of Politics and History: Volume 54, Number 1, 2008, pp. 1-15.

Spelman, Elizabeth V. 1998. “Aristotle and the Politicization fo the Soul,” in Sterba, James (Ed.). 1998. Social and Political Philosophy: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. Second edition. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 74-82.

Sterba, James (Ed.). 1998. Social and Political Philosophy: Classical Western Texts in Feminist and Multicultural Perspectives. Second edition. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co.

Struhl, Karsten J. 1975. Ethics in Perspective:  A Reader. New York: Random House.

Thurman, Howard. 1981. With Head and Heart: the Autobiography of Howard Thurman.

[Thiruvalluvar], Tirukkural. 1982. English Translation and Commentary by G. U. Pope, W. H. Drew, John Lazarus and F. W. Ellis. First published by W.H. Allen, & Co, 1886, Reprinted by The South India Saiva Siddhantha Works Publishing Society, Tinnevelly, Madras, India , 1962, 1982. Accessed online through Project Madurai, https://www.projectmadurai.org/pm_etexts/pdf/pm0153.pdf

Van Norden, Bryan. 2017. Taking Back Philosophy: A Multicultural Manifesto. New York: Columbia U. Press.

Waithe, Mary Ellen and Vicki Lynne Harper. 1987. “Late Pythagoreans: Theano II and Perictione II,” in Mary Ellen Waithe (Ed.), A History of Women Philosophers, Volume 1, 600 BC – 500 AD, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 41-48.

Yacob, Zera. “The Treatise of Zera Yacob,” in Daniel Bonevac (Ed.), Beyond the Western Tradition: Readings in Moral and Political Philosophy. Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Publishing Co.

Yancy, George. 1998. African-American Philosophers: 17 Conversations. New York: Routledge.

Whitehead, Alfred North, David Ray Griffin, and Donald W. Sherburne. 1985. Process and reality: an essay in cosmology. New York: Free Press.

Wilderson, Frank B., III. 2020. Afropessimism. New York: Liveright Publishing Corp., 2020. Kindle.

Anthony Sean Neal is an Associate Professor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy and Religion and a Faculty Fellow in the Shackouls Honors College of Mississippi State University. He is a 2019 inductee into the Morehouse College Collegium of Scholars and a Fellow with the American Institute for Philosophical and Cultural Thought. Dr. Neal received his doctorate in Humanities from Clark Atlanta University. He also received his Master of Divinity degree from Mercer University and a Bachelor’s degree from Morehouse College. Dr. Neal is the author of two books, Common Ground: A Comparison of the Idea of Consciousness in the Writings of Howard Thurman and Huey Newton (Africa World Press, 2015). The second book is entitled, Howard Thurman’s Philosophical Mysticism: Love Against Fragmentation (Lexington, 2019). He serves on the editorial board of The Acorn: Philosophical Studies in Pacifism and Nonviolence.

Greg Moses is editor of The Acorn: Philosophical Studies in Pacifism and Nonviolence and author of Revolution of Conscience: Martin Luther King, Jr. and the Philosophy of Nonviolence. He has co-edited a book with Gail Presbey: Peace Philosophy and Public Life: Commitments, Crises, and Concepts for Engaged Thinking. His research interests include the pluralist philosophy of Alain Locke, the peace philosophy of James Farmer, Sr., the concept of “Evolutionary Love” in Charles S. Peirce, and, more recently, the Howard School of religious humanism as exemplified by William Stuart Nelson. He teaches Ethics and the Philosophy of Nonviolence at Texas State University.

 Gail Presbey is Professor of Philosophy at University of Detroit Mercy, and Director of the James Carney Latin American Solidarity Archives. She engages in interdisciplinary work that involves philosophy, world history, oral history, and political theory. Her areas of expertise are philosophy of nonviolence and African philosophy, with current studies and research on Africa, Latin America, Mohandas Gandhi’s movement, feminism, and Pan-Africanism. She has researched in Kenya, South Africa, Ghana, India, and Brazil, having received several Fulbright grants. She has four edited books and over fifty articles and book chapters published. She has been Executive Director and then President of Concerned Philosophers for Peace (2003-2010). She is currently Secretary of the Peace History Society. Visit her home page at https://sites.udmercy.edu/gailpresbey/

Previous
Previous

Short Film - Charles de Agostin

Next
Next

Suffer a sea-change - Joshua Elwood